Proposition   The denumerable union of disjoint (in our book, pairwise disjoint) countable nonempty sets are denumerable. (Why add the condition of nonemptiness?)





Proof. Let , , ... be all the given sets. Then we know that each is in the form


Then the mapping , where is in the "domain" of , is bijective. Hence its image must be a subset of . Moreover, forms a denumerable set. Hence a previous example yields that is denumerable.







Proposition   The denumerable union of countable sets is countable.





Proof. Let , , ... be all given sets. Set


Then is pairwise disjoint. So



is a denumerable union of disjoint countable sets. It'll be countable. (When is it non-denumerable? Can it even be empty?)




    Hence



Proposition   The countable union of countable sets is countable.







Here is a criterion for countability, which might or might not be useful.





Proposition   A set is countable if and only if .





Proof. If is denumerable, then and hence . If if finite, then because . Conversly, Let be one-to-one from into . Let . Then



(a) If contains no maximum, then (why?). Since , we obtain that . Since is onto , it follows that .

(b) If contains a maximum, say . Then . Hence is equinumerous to some (why? This might be proved by induction.). Similarly, the assertion is proved by .




















Next, we consider sets with power of continuum. ("The set has power of continuum" means that )



Proposition   for times, has the power of continuum.





Proof. Denote



It's shown that . Suppose that . Let and be bijections. Write



Then define as



is then one-to-one and onto.








What is the connection between the natural number set and the real number set in the sense of cardinality (the "number" of elements in a set)?? In fact, a thoroughly obvervation would tell us the following proposition.



Proposition   and





Proof. Define the mapping by , and the mapping by in binary where if and only if while all other decimal digits are 0. Hence and play roles as injections in both directions. Schrder Bernstein (Be careful for the spelling!) Theorem says that .



The other assertion is similar. Take as the mapping who maps a subset of to the function such that if and only if . Another mapping is chosen to map a function to the subset . They both are injection (Verify it!). Therefore Schrder Bernstein leads us to the conclusion.





Through the same argument, we derive the following proposition.




Proposition   for any set .





Proof. Define the mapping who maps a subset of to the function such that if and only if . Another mapping is chosen to map a function to the subset . They both are injection and then we prove the equinumerosity.

















As an important remark, I have to mention which sets we have compared about their sizes. Indeed, we have the following types of discussion.


























(i)    .
(ii)   
(iii)   
(iv)    .
(v)   .









Note    I have to emphasize the meaning of the notation for a given set . Recall that we use Order Pairs as elements in the product sets of given sets, namely


and an interesting notion for an order pair is that, we might view it as a function ! By this I mean, after we define


the concept about an order pair is illustrated.



The notation seems to express all "infinite order pairs". Comparing with above, if stands for a finite sequence, it is natural to convent that means an infinite sequence, i.e.




Directly thinking, we finally define . In particular, if we choose , then , all sequences in .











Next, what are worth thinking for a while are the equinumerosity and the "dominance" . Indeed, imitating Cantor's diagonal method for real numbers, we can show that is uncountable. However, we still have no idea about whether it has power of continuum.



So we postpone the proof and then show the later assertion first.







Proposition  





Proof. We ought to define an injection throughout decimal expressions. For , write


Then we define . We know is injective (Show!), and we can easily find a converse injection. Hence Schrder Bernstein Theorem concludes the equinumerosity.







Proposition  





Proof. Since


immediately we have .















At last, I shall show two essential properties for sets with large cardinality.



Definition   is defined as all functions from to . is defined as all functions from continuously to .

In all my articles, is defined as all functions from to ; is defined as all functions from to .



Proposition   .





Proof. Assume (Why ??). Let be such a bijection. Define a function such that for ,



(This is the "diagonal argument" on continuum.) We know that . For , since , we have that . This means , a contradiction.










Problem   Is or ?? [改自台灣某知名大學碩士班入學考題]









Proposition (Cantor)   For every set , , or equivalently, .





Proof. We prove the later type. Denote . Assume (Why ??). Let be such a bijection. Define a function such that for ,



We know that . For , since , we have that . This means , a contradiction.